Contracts and You
The philosophy known as Contractarianism has many practical applications in
existing societies, but is wholly inadequate when used to examine the birth of civilization
and government, as it ignores not only rational thought, but physical evidence. The purpose
of this report is to examine Contractarianism in some of it’s broad applications in modern
society, and also what is known as the theory of the original contract.
Firstly, it is necessary to examine the theory itself. Locke proposed, although not in
so many words, that government, a basic tenet of society [it is necessary to note that even
egalitarian societies have forms of government, even though they are not powerful or
centralized], originated as an agreement between the individual members of society. Many
philosophers, including David Hume, have criticized this standpoint, and rightly so. Aside
from the obvious logistical difficulties related to this view when dealing with a society of
any significant size, it takes for granted certain things about the emergence of society.
Perhaps the most identifiable of these assumptions; that government emerged as a
conscious act of choice, perhaps even a conscious choice between different styles of
government, is also among the easiest to argue against.
To begin with, this view presupposes that the people already had knowledge of
various styles of government, and were able to pick and choose which style suited them
best. This implies that somewhere along the line the people had either made contact with
these forms of government, or had tried them for themselves. The latter is paradoxical in
the context of Contractarianism, and so cannot be the case, and the former is highly
unlikely. If, however, the people had come in contact with various forms of government, it
begs the question, how did those other governments form, and which among them was the
first? Obviously the first government had neither come in contact with any others, or tried
any other style of government, so therefore there was no menu from which to choose, and
therefore a case can be made against Contractarianism on that point.
The theory of conscious choice also presupposes that the people were unhappy with
their current lifestyle, and does not take into account outside pressures, such as simple
economics or religion. The group of people known as the Mayans, for example, were
actually much like the early Greeks, not one civilization so much as many in close
proximity to one another. The Tikal Mayans, for example, are believed to have formed their
civilization and early government around the priesthood, who are believed to have been in
relied on for information regarding agriculture, specifically when to plant, and when to
harvest. Haviland writes,
The dependence of the population in and around Tikal
upon their priesthood to manipulate supernatural beings
and forces on their behalf, in order that their crops would
not fail, tended to keep them in or near the city, in spite
of the fact that a slash-and-burn method of agriculture,
which was probably the prevailing method in early Tikal’s
history, requires the constant shifting of plots and
consequently tended to disperse the population over large
areas.
[Haviland, p. 320]
While it is true that Locke himself did not have access to this information, as Tikal was
only excavated in the mid 1950's, if a modern criticism is to be made, then it must be made
with modern information. The kind of religious dependance seen in the Tikal Mayans is
common in early civilizations, and indeed in some societies today, and cannot be ignored
when speculating about the emergence of government, as it can be a vital factor in the way
people behave.
However, the example of the Tikal Mayans also brings up the subject of economic
pressures, which helped to fuel their religious fervor. The Tikal Mayans were very worried
about food production, and rightly so. They most likely did not feel that they had much in
the way of choice when it came to relying on the priesthood for agricultural advice. It is
most likely that they felt the only other option was starvation, which is against the instinct
for survival, and therefore is not truly an option at all in this particular context. Locke
seems to have ignored the possibility that the formation of government was reactionary, in
response to the threat of starvation or such.
Another assumption that Locke makes, is that the contract, if there was one, would
extend to the offspring of those who made the contract. In other words, the people who
formed the government through mutual agreement were also binding their children and
grandchildren and all subsequent generations to that contract, which is not strictly speaking,
a contract. The subsequent generations are not voluntarily entering into the agreement, and
therefore it is not a contract for them, it is instead very nearly enslavement, in the sense
that they are bound by terms they did not themselves agree to.
Hume is quick to point out that government, while in some sense may have been
voluntary, was not formed by sitting down and discussing the options, but rather came to be
a "habitual ... acquiescence of the people." [Narveson, LPP, p.56] This view is not at all
compatible with Locke’s proposal, but at the same time is much more logical, given the
size of most early civilizations. The logistics of any other method would have been
unimaginably complex, and almost certainly beyond the capabilities of most peoples of the
time, since many of them had yet to develop even the most crude systems of writing.
If even these somewhat basic arguments can be levied against Contractarianism, is it
even possible for the philosophy to survive? The answer is yes, although one must
disregard the theory of the original contract. Since contracts are used every day in every
single society, in one form or another, then there obviously must be a place for contract
theory.
Certain aspects of government can be benfited by incorporating Contractarianism.
For example if the government were to ever consider employing it’s citizens, it would
obviously have to form contracts with them. Contracts are also a necessary part of dealing
with other nations. Contracts can prevent international conflict, lower trade barriers, and
increase at least the appearance of human rights, which is actually more important than it
may sound, at least from the standpoint of the government.
There is also the point to consider that while the ideal and rational government may
be separated from it’s country’s major religion, it must be acknowledged that this is not
always the case, and that these systems, however unreasonable we may find them, must be
dealt with as they are for now. Governments in this situation may find it necessary to
encourage their citizens to form personal contracts with their god or gods, in fact, if the
goal of the governing body is to control it’s citizens, the government may even suggest what
that contract should be. Again, while this may not be the ideal form of government, it must
at least be explored, since such regimes have existed in the past, exist today, and will most
likely continue to exist in the future.
While many may dismiss Contractariansim out of course, it is important to realize
that while it may not be an adequate philosophy with which to run a complex, efficient, and
fully functional government, it may still have it’s benefits if properly explored in a modern
context. However, Contractarianism as a theory to explain the rise of government and
civilization, it is extremely ineffective, and should be totally discarded. The theory defies
the logistical capabilities of even today’s societies with modern technology and techniques
for transferring information. It fails to take into account problems which arise so
consistently throughout human history that they might very well be referred to as historical
mainstays, problems such as economic pressures and the religious beliefs of the populace.
And even though aspects of the human psyche may defy reason and logic, it is important
that we not forgot to include them as factors, since we may not simply ignore that which
does not easily fit into our theories.
|
Non-Fiction
UW Owns ACM Contest
Contracts and You
There Is No Spoon
Machine Mind
Free Will in Slaughterhouse Five
Letter to Katrina
Monkey Business
|